Our institution is coming to life in a world of conflict. Everywhere, under the inspiration and guidance of certain philosophical, economic, political and sociological doctrines, there are people bent on the violent destruction of men and women and their institutions.
What should be the role of an institution of higher learning coming to life in such a world? It certainly should not be to attempt to pacify groups in conflict, or even less to join any of them. The commitment of universities everywhere is not to the passing, rather to the permanent aspects of human life. As such, universities need to place themselves beyond the conflicts of their time so that science and academic freedom -which mankind will need at all times- may be preserved.
What we suggest here is that the traditional ivory tower not be abandoned by scholars seeking to join the heated discussions of the political arena, but rather that the ivory tower be transformed into a new and transparent crystal tower that will allow scholars -professors and students- to watch, to think about and to critically study present conditions, in an effort to discover the probable shape of the future.
Francisco Marroquin University will emphasize the theoretical rather than the "practical" or "occupational" aspects of higher education.
The disdain for the study of theory in universities throughout the world is due, in part at least, to an incomplete understanding of the fact that all human thought finds its raison d'être in some form of action or practice. In the final analysis all knowledge, whether the most general and abstract or the most specific and concrete, consists of knowing how to do something.
However, it does not follow that practice ought to replace the study of theory. Indeed, every practice involves the application of one theory or another, whether or not this is known by the person who acts. The difference between those who learn to apply a theory without knowing what theory they are applying and those who apply it knowingly is that the latter are in a position to look for alternative methods which are compatible with the theory.
Obviously, the purpose of emphasizing theory is not to separate theory from practice; rather it is to provide the necessary foundations so that practice becomes flexible, more thoughtful, freer and more effective.
Those who are not aware of the theoretical foundations of their professional activity will not be able to go beyond the methods or techniques that they learned to apply, nor will they be in a position to discover anything new in their professional field. They will not have received, strictly speaking, a higher education -they will simply have acquired the necessary skills to perform certain tasks. It is not necessary, however, for universities to teach these skills since technical schools exist throughout the world to do precisely that.
Theoretical education, which necessarily involves practice, attempts to provide the basis for a vision that goes beyond the present in space and time; a vision which widens horizons instead of narrowing them, and which makes for intellectual modesty rather than arrogance and intolerance, the products of a narrow outlook and limited knowledge.
The disdain for theory and the emphasis on the "practical" have had a decisive influence on university instruction and on the contemporary academic philosophy of many universities. Many believe, for instance, that humanistic studies ought to be replaced by technical studies that have an immediate application to social development. This thinking has contributed to the idea that universities are centers for the study of specific techniques.
Human society has always felt the need to create and support institutions of higher learning, dedicated to teaching and to the search for principles or theories whose practical consequences may contribute to a better way of living. We believe that although the training of technicians in different fields is an important function which centers of higher learning must perform, it is not less true that universities, by definition and universal tradition, are and have been much more than centers for the training of technicians. Research is essential to academic work, and the teaching of techniques is essential to the work of technical schools. Since principles and theories do have practical consequences which are important for society to take advantage of, it is critical for society to teach techniques of application.
In the field of the natural sciences, the advance of knowledge has been so great that most universities in Latin America could dedicate themselves less to research in the natural sciences and more to the training of technicians in the application of the principles of those sciences -without greatly harming the advance of knowledge in these fields. After all, the majority of people in the world live in underdeveloped societies, where a great many practical applications of scientific principles (discovered long ago) have scarcely been put into practice. Thus, in these countries the application of old scientific principles rather that the search for new ones seems to be the more urgent task.
However, in the field of the social sciences, the situation is quite different. The difference is not merely that progress in the social sciences has been small when compared to the natural sciences, or that the principles of the social sciences are not applied to advantage, as evidenced by the poverty, the uneasiness and the convulsions that plague many regions of the world today. The fact is that, unlike in the case of sciences such as physics and chemistry, there is disagreement as to the very nature and scope as science of philosophy, economics, sociology and politics. Disagreements concerning specific theories are no less notorious. Under these circumstances, what is important is to re-examine and to re-formulate theories and principles rather than to train technicians in their application, for it is the validity of the principles themselves that is in question.
For this reason -and by way of example- the curriculum of the School of Law will emphasize the study of human rights -their nature and foundations, or philosophy- rather than the study of legislation and the auxiliary sciences such as sociology. Likewise, the curriculum of the School of Economics will emphasize the study of economic theory rather than accounting and other disciplines auxiliary to economics.
Through its teaching and publications, the new University will try to examine, critically and objectively, the theories that have had a decisive influence on contemporary social organization. It is the University's hope that as a result of a broad, free and rigorous training its graduates will contribute to the adoption by our society of policies of collective improvement, within the framework of the fundamental values of Western civilization.
All education, from elementary to higher, tries to provide human beings with what they need to fully develop their constructive capacities, and thereby prepare them to be able to search for their own satisfactory way of life. One of these capacities, the sum total of the rest, is the potential to live peacefully with other human beings. However, peaceful coexistence requires that we all make an effort so that reason is paramount in all aspects of human life. This means, among other things, that we all make an effort that the ideas of others be respected, since no one holds a monopoly on truth. We must also be willing to respect the rights of others, as human beings and citizens, as the only way to live in peace.
The violence of our time constitutes evidence of the decline of human reason throughout the world and, consequently, of the worldwide failure of education. As we have suggested, the rational capacity of man is manifest not only in his search for adequate means to certain ends. It is also manifest in the value he assigns to those ends. It is not necessary to argue for the view that not all that man is in a position to reach is valuable, for it would be enough to recall that from the very beginning man has had at his disposal adequate means to destroy himself.
Today's university must face the challenge of the universal crisis of human reason. When reason's voice is weak, everything is threatened. Liberty, peace, civilization are threatened. Indeed, the very life of man as a species is threatened.
As we have pointed out, the crisis of human reason reveals itself through violence. Violent actions, especially those that are political in nature, are motivated by specific interpretations and valuations of given social conditions; they do not spring from social conditions themselves, as some suggest. Man cannot act unless he does so on the basis of an interpretation -however rudimentary- and all interpretations are in principle capable of being mistaken. To assume that man can react automatically or instinctively (that is without the mediation of an interpretation or valuation -not only to simple physical stimuli such as rays of light and changes in temperature, but also to such complex stimuli as a whole social environment) is to make an evidently false assumption. Men react in identical or almost identical ways to physical stimuli, but to social, political, artistic or religious conditions their reactions vary considerably.
The crisis of human reason is also revealed in the rejection or unthinking abandonment of some of the fundamental values of Western civilization, such as peace, the infinite value of the person, freedom and the respect for property. As sources of rights and obligations, these values have made peaceful coexistence possible. Such values, contrary to what some people think, have been discovered rather than invented, by persons of great wisdom. Thus, it is neither through the arbitrary decisions of rulers nor the pressure of ruling groups that these values have become instituted. And their validity has nothing to do with the age in which they have been discovered. For example, many features of the Greco-Christian philosophy of man and life have greater significance for our time than some of the later experiences of humanity including, undoubtedly, certain aspects of our contemporary experience.
However, just as it is not the antiquity of the classical experience that determines its validity, so it is not the contemporaneity of ours that determines its invalidity. Perhaps the contemporary experience of man and life will become "classical" for coming generations. That will depend on our achieving greater depth and scope in our understanding of mankind.
How can a university face the challenge of the universal crisis of reason? We are convinced that it can do so only through serene and rigorous academic work in an environment of absolute intellectual freedom.
In most contemporary societies, the young are under pressure to become involved in collective movements of one kind or another. For this very reason it is important that they have the opportunity to discover the why and wherefore of their involvement. Youth is combative, youth is enthusiastic. However, few things can be more harmful for a social conglomerate than the alliance of belligerent enthusiasm with ignorance.
If due to their nature young people are enthusiastic and idealistic, it is the job of those who once were young to guide them so that their enthusiasm may be beneficial rather than harmful to themselves and to society at large.
The endeavor to attain self-perfection is the only task which is under the effective control of each individual, and which necessarily benefits others. It is also the end toward which education, at any level, can contribute. Education that seeks to contribute to the search for human perfection must be an education that guarantees the free analysis and discussion of diverse ideas and values. It must be an education in which learning is fundamentally a process of self-discovery rather than the mechanical absorption of ideas or principles. In short, it must be a process that strengthens and guides the natural inclinations of men and women in their attempt to understand themselves and their surrounding world. Poor education -that is the process that does not allow the free exercise of the rational capacity of those that are to be educated- is worse than the absence of systematic education. Common sense left to itself has a better and deeper reach than common sense which has been deformed by poor educational institutions, something we see confirmed in all aspects of life.
Higher education has always fought against prejudice and ignorance and has subjected popular myths to rigorous rational analysis. Its function has been fundamentally of an intellectual nature. We believe that higher education cannot have any other function in our time. What is more, we believe it is urgent that it have this function.
Contemporary tendencies to weigh down universities with moral and political responsibilities reveal the crisis of our time. And those tendencies, besides being erroneous in principle (as will be pointed out below), jeopardize the work of the Academy, for they can easily transform classrooms, from laboratories in search of truth into soap boxes for one or another political faction. The moral responsibility of universities does not go beyond cultivating the love for the search for truth and for academic freedom.
The contentious world we live in demands that we return to the classical or fundamental idea of a university: an institution of learning, of teaching and of research that is dedicated through its organization, orientation and function to academic excellence, and which has nothing to do with the deliberate search for solutions to the social problems of the moment.
Since this statement can so easily create misunderstanding, no sooner has it been said, than it is necessary to offer some explanations. Why is it necessary to emphasize that universities, because of their nature, are beyond the deliberate search for solutions to the social problems of the moment? The belief that it is the business of universities to look for solutions to these problems necessarily leads to the idea that it is the function of universities to carry out activities which correspond to government offices, which is evident even through a superficial analysis of the phrase "solutions to social problems".
The concept of solution does not have the same meaning within the context of social problems as it has within the context of scientific problems. Scientific problems are solved when someone presents a true description or theory. This is not so in the case of social problems. The solution of social problems requires (besides the pertinent information) the concerted action of groups or parties and, thereby, direct or indirect participation in a political process. It is not hard to imagine that even if universities throughout the world found solutions to the scientific aspects of the principle social problems, the world would remain underdeveloped because the required political action to solve them was lacking. Many believe, for example, that the science of economics long ago discovered the road that people must follow if they want to improve their lives; nevertheless, people have not traveled that road.
Therefore, if one insists that it is the direct or indirect function of universities to concern themselves with the solution of social problems, one is saying, though not explicitly, that the function of the university is political besides academic. This idea has the most harmful consequences for academic work, some of which will be discussed below.
On the other hand, if when one asserts that universities ought to worry about the solution to social problems, all one wants to say is that they should study economic, political, juridical and sociological questions that have a direct bearing on the solutions to social problems, then it is really not something worth saying.
The history of higher education shows that universities have always made important contributions to social welfare; additionally, that such contributions have never been the result of the "social sensitivity" or the concern of university people with solving the problems of their society. Such contributions have always been the result of "scientific sensitivity" -the devotion to the search for truth- as is clearly shown by the history of science. It could even be said that the social efficacy of academic work has been inversely proportional to the scholars' concern for the social conditions of the time in which they live.
It is not hard to find the reason for this. As we have suggested, the idea that it is the business of universities to worry about solving social problems necessarily involves the confusion of politics and academics. This confusion, which has been evident in most public universities in Latin America for more than half a century (and which threatens to "politicize" universities in other parts of the world), has only prevented universities from being socially efficient. By adopting political methods and criteria for the selection of personnel, for administration and for the evaluation of academic work, these universities have notoriously harmed teaching and research- precisely those university activities that are of collective benefit. The external or internal "politicization" of universities not only threatens the advance and diffusion of knowledge, it also threatens academic freedom.
As everyone knows, the political mind is basically interested in group or party action. This type of action cannot be carried out without common criteria, whatever the nature of such criteria. Politicians engage in "dialogues" in order to make deals, to agree upon courses of action, to see to it that a certain policy is adopted; however, they are not interested in "dialogues" to understand or discover truth. Politicians assume that they know the truth; their very profession demands this. Politicians, qua politicians, are interested neither in science nor art. Thus "academic politician" is a contradiction in terms.
For these reasons a university that is "politicized", externally or internally, is in danger of increasingly taking on the characteristics of a political party and of increasingly losing those of a place of higher learning. This is especially true if political activity is a main source of employment and social prestige, as is often the case in Latin America.
As we have seen, if one believes that it is the responsibility of universities to worry about solutions to social problems, one is naturally led to confuse the categories of politics and academics. We have already pointed out some of the implications this idea has for academic work. In addition, the idea that it is a primary or secondary function of the university to worry about solutions to social problems naturally implies the notion that universities are centers of social service -dispensaries of culture, instead of centers of opportunity for individual improvement and for the training of leaders in science and culture.
The implications of conceiving universities as centers of social service are as clear and harmful as the implications of thinking that universities have political responsibilities or that they should carry out activities that belong to state offices.
Centers of social service are created to give various types of assistance, according to clearly defined criteria, indiscriminately to those who request it. On the other hand, universities (whether or not they are state institutions) are not created to serve their community -despite the fact that they do serve the community when they efficiently perform their academic function.
What is being denied when one asserts that universities do not exist to serve their community? One is denying that universities can both fulfill their academic function and, at the same time, respond to a will that assigns them a specific service. If we asked ourselves the reason for their being or the what for of their existence, we would have to answer that universities exist to transmit and to search for advanced knowledge; to advance and strengthen the arts and the sciences; to raise the cultural level of the community -all of this guided by the conviction that scientific and cultural progress result in collective benefit, as evident from the positive impact of universities on their societies and the world at large.
However, the following could be argued,
Granting it is true that, in general, universities are at the service of the arts and the sciences, why can it not be equally true to assert that they exist to serve their community? Why do people search for and transmit knowledge? Is it not to benefit their community, to serve it? Is it possible to justify the existence of universities in any other way?
Those who assert that universities exist to serve the community are not
really answering the question concerning the reason for the existence of universities. Instead, what they have in mind are the benefits which, as a matter of course, university work provides society. A moment's reflection is enough to make clear that it is only in an indirect or derived sense that universities exist to serve their community. Indeed, when they fulfill their function well, they do serve their community.
Consider the following example:
Judicial power exists to administer justice, and we would all agree that the administration of justice benefits everyone. However, what would happen if judges believed that their function was not merely to administer justice impartially, but also to "serve" the community? Would they be, by virtue of such motivation, in a better position to administer justice? What would happen if the judge qua judge were motivated by considerations regarding the consequences of his judicial decision for society -considerations which are foreign to the law? Is it not reasonable to think that the criteria of impartiality, universality and certainty which are essential to the administration of justice would be weakened or diluted when mixed with criteria which are logically more distant and far less clear and precise? Is it not equally reasonable to think that because of this the administration of justice would suffer and, consequently, so would social well-being? Justice serves society, but the judge serves justice.
The application of these considerations to the function of universities, and especially to the work of professors, seems to us clear and straightforward. Science serves society, but the university serves science.
There are also other reasons, both theoretical and practical, for holding that it is a mistake to think that universities exist to serve their community. The concept of "institutional obligation" (which is implicit in the idea that at least part of the mission of universities is to provide social services, and which is explicitly expressed in ideas about the obligations of abstract entities) originated in the attribution of obligations to personalized collectives such as The State, The Church or The University. These obligations, however, are primarily those of individuals.
It is evident that, strictly speaking, only individuals can have obligations. The personification of abstract entities, which is so common in ordinary language, can be seen in expressions such as "The State ought to try...", or "The Church is concerned about...", or "The University wants to make it known...". This is a logical mistake which ordinarily goes unnoticed because it generally does not create any confusion. In most cases it is simply a question of inexact use of language and does not generate any theoretical inferences or have any practical consequences.
On the other hand, when this type of personification provides the starting point or basis for a doctrine, it is worthwhile noting especially since it appears that the personification of The State and The Collective lies at the ideological root of totalitarian doctrines and of contemporary ideas about the obligations of society.
As we have suggested, the value of the social service rendered by universities is and has always been in direct proportion to their academic excellence and not to their "social sensitivity". And it is precisely academic excellence that is placed at risk when institutions of higher education are conceived as institutions of social service.
The concepts of "service", "redemption" or "liberation" of the people or society presuppose the existence of someone who deserves our compassion; someone from whom little ought to be asked and to whom it is necessary to give generously. Social service is, fundamentally, the fulfillment of moral obligations by the person who serves; it does not imply the fulfillment of requisites or the exercise of responsibilities by the one being served, as is the case with higher education.
If, as it seems, even the fulfillment of moral and social obligations involves some kind of selection or choice, one must not be surprised at the fact that the opportunity to receive a higher education is selective by nature. We all know that universities throughout the world differentiate between those who are capable and those who are incapable of taking advantage of the opportunity of personal improvement that higher education represents.
Consequently, if one is to accept the idea that social service is a basic function of universities, rather than an indirect or derived one, then one would have to reduce the inevitable differentiation to its lowest level, offering the opportunity of university study to all who fulfill minimum requirements, such as having a high school diploma. University work would also have to be adapted to the conditions and interests of the students, instead of asking the students to satisfy the requirements of the university. The university would have to lower itself to their level instead of fixing a level at which students must aim.
It is well-known that excellence in the sciences and the arts is not something everyone seeks, and that not all who seek it can attain it, due to the inclinations and limitations of each individual. In order to be consistent with their orientation, those universities which are conceived fundamentally as centers of social service will have to sacrifice the ideal of academic excellence. Paradoxically, in their attempt to live up to a mistaken ideal of social service, they will thereby diminish their chances of being socially effective.
By academic freedom we understand the right of persons or groups of persons to teach any art or science. Thus, Francisco Marroquin University has the right to decide the contents of the courses it offers in view of what it holds to be true, false, useful or irrelevant and which can be taught within the time the student has to complete his degree requirements.
As is to be expected in any private institution,
the professors to whom the University has assigned
such an important task enjoy the confidence of its
authorities, because their academic and teaching
views are similar to those of the University and
the course content that they teach has its approval.
The Board of Trustees, the highest authority of the University, evaluates the faculty from time to time in order to ascertain if that which the University teaches is in accordance with what the Trustees wish to offer to those who choose to enroll.
Professors are free to teach or not what the University requests. Those professors who agree to teach what the University wishes become members of the faculty.
Francisco Marroquin University recognizes the academic freedom of any faculty member to teach that which is contrary to the University's philosophy or its policies, as long as this is done elsewhere and under someone else's auspices. Consequently, only those professors who choose to teach what the University requires of them become and remain members of its faculty.
Licenciatura in Architecture. Universidad de San Carlos; Guatemala.
SCHOOL OF ECONOMIC SCIENCES
JOSE RAUL GONZALEZ jrg@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Business Administration. Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala. - MBA. Universidad de Rochester; U.S.A.
SCHOOL OF LAW
MILTON ARGUETA margueta@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Law. Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala. - Ph.D. in Law. Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala.
SCHOOL OF MEDICINE
RODOLFO HERRERA-LLERANDI llerandi@ufm.edu.gt
- B.S. in Biology. Massachusetts Institute of Technology; U.S.A. - M.D., Harvard University; U.S.A. - Specialization in General Surgery, Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery, Harvard University; U.S.A.
SCHOOL OF DENTISTRY
RAMIRO ALFARO odontologia@ufm.edu.gt
- Dental Surgeon. Universidad de San Carlos; Guatemala. - Specialization in Oral Maxilofacial Surgery. University of Pennsylvania; U.S.A. - Doctor F.A.D.I. (Fellow Academy Dentistry International). Pennsylvania; U.S.A.
GRADUATE SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS AND BUSINESS ADMINISTRATION (ESEADE)
JOSE RAUL GONZALEZ (See School of Economic Sciences)
ACADEMIC DIRECTORS
SCHOOL OF NUTRITION
JORGE TULIO RODRIGUEZ joturo@ufm.edu.gt
- M.D., Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala. - Specialization in Pediatric Gastroenterology and Nutrition. Baylor College of Medicine; U.S.A.
GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES
ARMANDO DE LA TORRE delatorre@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Classical Languages. Universidad de Comillas; Spain. - Licenciatura in Philosophy. Universidad de Comillas; Spain. Licenciatura in Theology. University of Frankfurt; Germany. Ph.D. in Philosophy. University of Munich; Germany.
INSTITUTE OF POLITICAL SCIENCE AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
CARROLL RIOS DE RODRIGUEZ eepp@ufm.edu.gt
- B.A. in Government modified with Economics. Dartmouth College, New Hampshire; U.S.A. M.A. in Latin American Studies. Georgetown University, Washington, D.C.; U.S.A.
DEPARTMENT OF PSYCHOLOGY
LUIS RECINOS lar@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Psychology. Brandeis University; U.S.A. - M.A. in Experimental Psychology. New School for Social Research; U.S.A. Ph.D in Clinical Psychology. La Sorbonne; France. DEPARTMENT OF SECONDARY EDUCATION IN MATHEMATICS. PHYSICS. HUMANE STUDIES AND ART HISTORY
ARTURO HIGUEROS ahigueros@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Literature. Universidad del Valle; Guatemala.
ORGANIZATION FOR THE ARTS
GERALDINA BACA SPROSS orpafm@ufm.edu.gt
SCHOOL OF PUBLIC ACCOUNTING AND AUDITING
HUGO AREVALO pkguatemala@uole.com
- Licenciatura in Public Accounting and Auditing. Universidad de San Carlos; Guatemala. - M.B.A. University of California; U.S.A. - Graduate work in Finance Administration. University of París; France.
QUETZALTENGO CAMPUS
ANGEL RONCERO roncero@ufm.edu.gt
- Ph.D. in Theology. Universidad Pontificia Salesiana, Roma; Italy. - Licenciatura in Biblical Science. Pontificio Instituto Bíblico, Roma; Italy. - Doctor Honoris Causa in Social Sciences. Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala.
Popol Vuh Museum
CURATOR
OSWALDO CHINCHILLA ofchinch@ufm.eu.gt
- Licenciatura in Archaeology. Universidad de San Carlos; Guatemala. Ph.D. in Anthropology. Vanderbilt University, Nashville Tennessee; U.S.A.
Ludwig Von Mises Library
GENERAL DIRECTOR
JULIO COLE jhcole@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Economics. Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala. M.A. in Economics. Universidad Francisco Marroquín; Guatemala. HENRY HAZLITT CENTER
JUAN CARLOS CACHANOSKY cachanosky@ufm.edu.gt
- Licenciatura in Economics. Universidad Católica Argentina; Argentina. - Ph.D. in Economics. International College; U.S.A.
Presented at the inauguration of Francisco Marroquin University, Guatemala City, on January 15, 1972 by the President of the University, Dr. Manuel F. Ayau.
We initiate today the realization of a dream, long cherished and enriched by each of the founders of Francisco Marroquin University. Some have generously donated part of their assets; others have sacrificed time from their vital activities; and others have given the University the form and structure necessary to bring about its realization. All have strengthened the dream with their faith in the youth and future of our country. To all of them, our profound gratitude.
I would like to focus on the relationships between institutions and the ideologies of those who direct them, but first I would make some general observations.
It is an accepted fact that man does not knowingly deceive himself; he attempts to use pure reason to avoid the contamination of prejudice. He knows that prejudice leads man to adopt the wrong means, and that the wrong means cannot lead to the right ends.
No one has a monopoly on truth. Men and women of goodwill who are working not only for their own benefit or for rewards in an afterlife, but also for the welfare of mankind, have many differences of opinion, due not to ill-will but to sincere disagreement over complex ideas. Such differences are constructive so long as they do not degenerate into violent intransigence. They afford us the opportunity to analyze our own convictions. Unless you understand the argument of he who disagrees with you better than he does, you cannot be sure that you are right. Of course, those who argue with people of ill-will waste their time. But, those who refuse to argue with people of goodwill forgo an opportunity to develop their intellect.
In the history of mankind, freedom of belief has, innumerable times, been defended with life itself. This is ample proof of the value that man has always placed on freedom of conscience, thought and expression.
Peace becomes impossible to obtain when someone tries to impose common beliefs on all. It is sometimes said that differences of opinion are in themselves the cause of conflict and must be eliminated, by force if necessary, in order to preserve peace. I believe that the reverse is true. Conflicts occur where diversity of ideas is not tolerated because, as an illustrious Mexican statesman said, peace is achieved through respecting other people's rights.
Certain ideological positions are mutually exclusive, such as socialism and liberal democracy. Nevertheless, both positions are defended by men and women of goodwill. These differences of opinion among people will necessarily be reflected in the character of the institutions that these people create.
Many institutions, such as universities, are directed by persons who, rightly or wrongly, believe in the validity of their convictions. Should they come to realize that it is some other theory that is valid, and if they are intellectually honest, they will change their opinions, and once again they will find themselves in the position of defending as valid those opinions which they hereafter hold as true.
Because every institutional hierarchy will judge new members according to the beliefs that those called upon to judge consider valid, it is only natural that in institutions there prevails a community of beliefs based on fundamental values. The converse situation would be as incongruous as a religious institution directed by atheists, or a socialist institution by liberals (believers in liberty). In either case, the authorities would not consider those persons who did not share the convictions "of the institution" as qualified.
We, the founders of the Francisco Marroquin University, hold as valid certain convictions and, although some of them are shared with us by directors of other universities, we have considered it necessary to found another. We believe that there should exist an opportunity for pursuing academic excellence different from those already in existence. An opportunity which differs regarding the philosophy of social order and the type of professional training that is conducive to the peaceful progress of civilizations.
Many of these ideas have already been published in the Philosophy of the University, but on this occasion, as President, I must be very frank about those convictions which I personally hold. This personal declaration is of interest for two reasons. First, because of the reasons I mentioned earlier, it is inevitable that the hierarchy of this University will be influenced by these convictions and, as a consequence, in some measure will serve to anticipate the character of the University. The second reason is that since I have been honored with the responsibilities of this office, such delegation implies that the founders have made their choice taking these convictions into account, which even if not shared by each and all with perfect uniformity, do reflect the spirit in which the University has been created, a spirit that must be made known to all of those who participate as donors, professors, administrators or students.
We firmly believe in the capacity of imperfect men to be better able to realize their destiny when free and not when compelled by the collective entity personified by the State.
We believe in individual rights. Freedom and property must always be respected, not only because they are innate to man, but also because of their utilitarian value to society. We do not think, therefore, that there exists any conflict between individual rights and social interest, as could exist between individual interest and general interest.
We believe that truth or justice cannot be discovered by counting votes. We believe in democracy, but we also hold that, whereas suffrage is an adequate method of determining the wishes of the majority and of deciding on matters of procedure, it is not the way to discover truth or justice.
We believe in the rule of law and not that of persons or groups of persons, be they a minority of a majority. We believe in lawful government based on abstract general rules of just conduct that do not discriminate because of race, religion or economic position and which allow people to plan their lives in the certainty that the results of their acts, when within the law, will be respected.
We believe that the spontaneous order which arises when persons act freely and peacefully to achieve their common material and spiritual ends is far superior to a designed social order imposed deliberately --a type of organization proper only to a business, a government or an army.
The mission of Universidad Francisco Marroquín is to teach and disseminate the ethical, legal, and economic principles of a society of free and responsible persons.
Characteristics
Founded in 1971. Private, secular, coeducational, nonresidential, nonprofit.
Degrees awarded
Associate, profesorado (for secondary school teachers), baccalaureus (artium and scienciae), licenciatura (licentiate), master, medical, dental, Ph.D.
Academic disciplines
Architecture, business administration, computer sciences, dentistry, education, economics, electronics, international relations, law, medicine, political science, public accounting, psychology, social sciences, systems engineering.
Enrollment 1998
Total
16,944
Undergraduate
5,406
Graduate
946
Medical/Dental
428
Non-degree
86
Distance education
10,078
Women
47%
Annual tuition fees
Undergraduate
$ 2,700-$3,600
Graduate
$ 3,200
Medical/Dental (nationals)
$ 4,300
Medical (foreigners)
$10,800
Dental (foreigners: Latin Americans/others)
$6,000/$12,300
Distance Education
$ 425-$ 575
Academic calendar
The academic year in Guatemala begins in January and ends in November. Undergraduate programs operate on a semester system; graduate and distance learning programs are on a quarter system. Undergraduate programs have a six-week semester break, from June to mid-July. Commencements are in May and November.
Admissions policy
UFM targets the brightest students for admission and it has the most rigorous entrance requirements in the country. The University is emphatic that selection of students be based solely on academic criteria. No information on ability to pay, ethnic, religious or other affiliations is requested at any point in the admissions process. Students of all religions are represented, as are members of Guatemala's Mayan ethnic community. Women generally comprise between 45% and 48% of the student body.
Admission requirements
Applications for all programs should be submitted mid-year for January admission. (Some programs allow mid-year admissions.) Requirements, forms, and deadlines vary from program to program. Required of all applicants are secondary school and/or other academic transcripts. Aptitude tests are required by all baccalaureus and licenciatura programs. These tests are administered in June, July, and October, and November on campus. Many programs require additional exams. All inquiries and applications should be made directly to the school or department of interest.
Distance learning (Instituto de Educación Abierta - IDEA)
This program operates under the stewardship of the School of Computer Science. Admission is open to anyone with a secondary school diploma.
Language of instruction
Spanish. Knowledge of English is required of all students at the baccalaureus and licenciatura levels (acceptable TOEFL score is a degree requirement). Students at this level are expected to be able to handle reading assignments and lectures in English. Many key texts used at the University are available only in English, and this is often the language of instruction in seminars, courses, and lectures given by visiting professors.
Foreign admissions
Foreign students are welcome at UFM. Application procedures are the same as for local students. Transcripts may be presented in English. In the case of transfer students, academic credit for course equivalency may be available. To receive a university degree in Guatemala, foreign students must submit their secondary school diploma to the Ministry of Education for recognition and certification. Tuition and fees are the same for foreigners as for nationals, with the exception of medicine and dentistry.
Handicapped access
The School of Computer Science has a program in data entry designed for handicapped persons. The program is free of charge. Qualified students who wish to continue on in a full degree program are encouraged to do so, and are given a full scholarship. UFM is the only university in Guatemala with such a program, and its campus the only one purposefully designed to fully accommodate the physical needs of the handicapped.
Financial aid
Deferred tuition; scholarships; tuition waiver for staff and children of faculty.
Campus
UFM is located in the heart of Guatemala City's most prestigious residential and business area. Built on over 40 acres in a wooded ravine, the campus is protected from the hustle and bustle of the city, and has ample parking with controlled access. Principal academic buildings are library, student center, and academic center (housing classrooms and administration). A large cultural complex includes the Ixchel Museum of Indian Costume, the Popol-vuh Museum (Mayan archeology), a 600-seat auditorium, and a seminar center. Like all universities in Guatemala, the campus has no dormitories. Most students live at home or with relatives, or rent lodging.
Internet access
UFM is an Internet service provider. It offers on-campus and dial-up service at lower-than-market rates exclusively to students, teachers, and administrators. All students with an account have on-campus access through computer labs and the library. All buildings on the campus are connected by a fiber optic intranet.
Governing boards
Board of trustees (fifty members) and board of directors (nine members).
Student associations
AIESEC (economics, Guatemalan chapter) Architecture Students Association Computer Science Students Association Coordinating Committee (of student associations) Economic Sciences Association (business administration) Economics Students Association FORUM (debate society) Guatemalan Association for International Law Honor Committee (law) Law Students Association Medical Students Association
Periodic publications
Law review(Revista de la Facultad de Derecho) Economics journal (Laissez-Faire)
Distance learning magazine (Futuro)